



全文预览已结束
下载本文档
版权说明:本文档由用户提供并上传,收益归属内容提供方,若内容存在侵权,请进行举报或认领
文档简介
是小柯论文网通过网络搜集,并由本站工作人员整理后发布的,是篇质量较高的学术论文,供本站访问者学习和学术交流参考之用,不可用于其他商业目的,的论文版权归原作者所有,因网络整理,有些文章作者不详,敬请谅解,如需转摘,请注明出处小柯论文网,如果此论文无法满足您的论文要求,您可以申请本站帮您代写论文,以下是正文。 abstract:study of humor discourse has attracted an increasingly numerousattention since 80s of last century. traditionally, they approach it mainly from pragmatic aspect. in this paper, i try a new research perspective, metonymic function and scenario concept to study how metonymic link works in the interpretation of humor as a cognitive and mental process.key words:humor metonymy speech act scenario.introductionas well known, the following is a dialogue between a customer and the waiter in a restaurant. customer: waiter, theres a fly in my soup!waiter: thats ok, the cook used to be a tailor. in traditional ways, this humor would be approached to from cooperative principles or ambiguity. the punch line of this humor is that the waiter does not behave cooperatively enough. cooperative principles do have the potential to explain the unsuccessful communication because of the uncooperativeness of the waiter, though it fails to explore why the waiter is not cooperative. in this paper, within the framework of speech act metonymy, i want to show how the theory provides a new angel to this problem.cognitive approach to metonymymetonymy has long been seen as a figure of speech in the language system. it suggests a relation of “stands for”. but cognitive linguistics point that metonymy is, like metaphor, a cognitive mechanism. it is a mapping of a cognitive domain, the source, onto another domain, the target. it is widely accepted that there are three types of metonymies: (1)prepositional metonymy-referential: there will be a conversation between washington and tokyo. this example shows a typical metonymy, a “stands for” and referential relation.(2)prepositional metonymy-predicational: a. mary was able to pass the exam.b: mary passed the exam.sentence a is mostly seen as an assertion of the ability of mary to pass the exam. but given a context, it can be a declaration of a fact of passing the exam, using potentiality to stand for actuality.(3)ocutionary metonymy: can you pass me the salt?this sentence apparently is an interrogative, but actually it functions as a request on the part of the hearer to perform some action. in this case, interrogative metonymically stands for request. it does not happen within the language system, but in the illocutionary force as in speech act theory, so this type of metonymy is also called speech act metonymy. .speech act metonymy and humor analysisthe theory of speech act metonymy provides us an account of the interpretation of indirect speech acts in terms of speech act scenarios, essentially idealized cognitive models of certain culturally entrenched activities, that include not only an event itself, but also knowledge about preconditions, results and consequences of this event. usually, a scenario of request consists of at least four parts: the before component: state the conditions that the action can happen proper, that is the premise for the speech act to have perlocutionary force; the core part, that describes the essential feature of the action itself, and then immediate result that obtains if the action is felicitously performed. finally, there is an after component, which describes the intended consequence of the action . the before h can do a.s wants h to do a.the core s puts h under a (more or less strong) obligation to do a.the result h is under an obligation to do a(h must/should/ought to do a).the afterh will do a.we assume that each component is metonymically linked to the speech act scenario as a whole. that is, the pragmatic function of each component can, to various degree stand for a request. as for “various degree”, it must be concerned with conceptual distance to the core on the part of each component. with the conceptual distance to the core being different, the pragmatic force to stand for a request accordingly changes. panther and thornburg proposed two hypotheses in terms of conceptual distance. in this paper, only the first hypothesis will be examined.hypothesis 1: the more distant the component of the scenario from the core, the weaker is the force to evoke the scenario, and the more is the inferencing effort on the hearer to know the real intention of the speaker.now it is the time to turn back to the humorous dialogue mentioned in the beginning of the paper. this communication is not successful in that the customer does not manage to convey his intention to the waiter. the utterance is not a declarative to announce a fact but stands for a request to remove the fly, change soup, or ask for explanation or repayment. the fact that this component of the scenario, according to hypothesis 1, distant to conceptual core, has weak strength of metonymic link to a request is the reason why the waiter does not get the real intention of the customer. so the waiter just gives some verbal explanation to the problem proposed by the customer, but no any action of remedy. if the customer chooses a component less distant to conceptual core than this, which therefore has stronger strength of metonymic link, such as you can remove the fly in my soup or something else, the waiter is sure to know what to do. .conclusionmetonymy, traditionally seen as a figure of speech, actually is a kind of cognitive mechanism by which people connect one thing in the world to another and this ability of association helps people draw inferences easily from implicit conversations. humor, as a discourse type, especially places heavy demands on the listeners inferencing work. therefore, it is a new and advisable trend to study humor in the metonymic frame. with the help of metonymies in the process of inferencing, the punch line of humor can be easily reached. references:1panther, klaus-uwe & thornburg, linda. a cognitive approach to inferencing in conversation, journal of pragmatics. 1998.2panther, klaus-uwe & thornburg, linda (eds).metonymy and pragmatic inferencing, john benjamins publishing company. 2003.3panther, klaus-uwe & gnter radden (eds). metonymy in language and thought. amsterdam: john benjamins. 1999.4李悦娥,范宏雅.话语分析.上海:上海外语教育出版社,2002.(作者单位:中国计量学院外国语学院)其他参考文献baker, sheridan. the practical stylist. 6th ed. new york: harper & row, 1985.flesch, rudolf. the art of plain talk. new york: harper & brothers, 1946.gowers, ernest. the complete plain words. london: penguin books, 1987.snell-hornby, mary. translation studies: an integrated approach. amsterdam: john benjamins, 1987.hu, zhuanglin. 胡壮麟, 语言学教程 m. 北京: 北京大学出版社, 2006.jespersen, otto. the philosophy of grammar. london: routledge, 1951.
温馨提示
- 1. 本站所有资源如无特殊说明,都需要本地电脑安装OFFICE2007和PDF阅读器。图纸软件为CAD,CAXA,PROE,UG,SolidWorks等.压缩文件请下载最新的WinRAR软件解压。
- 2. 本站的文档不包含任何第三方提供的附件图纸等,如果需要附件,请联系上传者。文件的所有权益归上传用户所有。
- 3. 本站RAR压缩包中若带图纸,网页内容里面会有图纸预览,若没有图纸预览就没有图纸。
- 4. 未经权益所有人同意不得将文件中的内容挪作商业或盈利用途。
- 5. 人人文库网仅提供信息存储空间,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对用户上传分享的文档内容本身不做任何修改或编辑,并不能对任何下载内容负责。
- 6. 下载文件中如有侵权或不适当内容,请与我们联系,我们立即纠正。
- 7. 本站不保证下载资源的准确性、安全性和完整性, 同时也不承担用户因使用这些下载资源对自己和他人造成任何形式的伤害或损失。
最新文档
- 煤场及计量设施租赁协议与煤场租赁合同3篇
- 高三克服焦虑课件
- 高一课本劝学课件
- 高一化学必修课课件
- 新旧房兼并交易合同:二手房买卖风险管控策略
- 离婚协议书中关于共同生活费用承担补充协议委托书
- 离婚协议书范本:财产分割与子女抚养及赡养协议
- 离婚宅基地房屋产权、使用权及补偿款分割协议
- 汽车制造私人工厂质量检测员劳务派遣合作协议
- 骶骨肿瘤影像课件
- YY 1727-2020口腔黏膜渗出液人类免疫缺陷病毒抗体检测试剂盒(胶体金免疫层析法)
- 粘膜免疫系统概述
- 10室外配电线路工程定额套用及项目设置
- 钢板桩及支撑施工方案
- 急救中心急救站点建设标准
- 冷藏车保温箱冰排使用记录
- 消防安全知识宣传-主题班会课件(共24张PPT)
- 幼儿园课件我从哪里来
- 高效液相色谱法-PPT课件
- 精细化学品化学-课件
- T∕CIS 71001-2021 化工安全仪表系统安全要求规格书编制导则
评论
0/150
提交评论