




免费预览已结束,剩余1页可下载查看
下载本文档
版权说明:本文档由用户提供并上传,收益归属内容提供方,若内容存在侵权,请进行举报或认领
文档简介
explain and discuss relevance theorys contention that grices generalized conversational implicatures should be re-analyzed as explicaturesintroductionthe concept of implicature was first introduced by grice, who defined implicature essentially as what is communicated less what is said. and this definition contributed in part to the proliferation of a lot of different species of implicature by neo-griceans. the relevance theorists have responded to this by proposing a shift back to the distinction between the explicit and implicit meaning. but they appear to have pared down the concept of implicature too much, and ignore phenomena that may be better treated as implicatures in their over-generalisation of the idea of explicature. these problems have their roots in the fact that explicit and implicit meaning intuitively overlap, and so dont provide a suitable basis for distinguishing implicature from other types of pragmatic phenomena. the alternative conceptualisation of implicature based on the concept of implying with that grice originally associated his notion of implicature is thus proposed. from this definition it emerges that implicature constitutes something else inferred by the addressee which is not literally said by the speaker. instead, it is meant in addition to what the literally speaker says, and consequently, it is defeasible like all other types of pragmatic phenomena.relevance theorys contentionsperber and wilson (1995: 182) introduced the concept of explicature, which was to complement the gricean concept of implicature, trying to show that pragmatic inferences contribute to what is implied and what is explicitly communicated. they defined the explicature as an explicit assumption communicated by an utterance that is a development of a logical form encoded by the utterance. carston has done much of the work in the relevance theory on explicit and implicit meaning (1988), and has expanded upon this definition of explicature in the following manner:“a propositional form communicated by an utterance which is pragmatically constructed on the basis of the propositional schema or template (logical form) that the utterance encodes; its content is an amalgam of linguistically decoded material and pragmatically inferred material” (carston 2000: 10).pragmatic processes involved in deriving explicatures include saturation, disambiguation, free enrichment, and ad hoc concept construction (carston 2000). the relevance theorists have thus done much to show that many different pragmatic processes are involved in developing what is encoded by the utterance into the propositions that are actually communicated.the implicature is also defined as “any other propositional form communicated by the utterance; its content consists of wholly pragmatically inferred matter” (carston 2000: 10). the definition of implicature follows from sperber and wilsons original assumption that any assumption communicated that is not explicit must be implicit, and thus must be an implicature (sperber and wilson 1995: 182). so implicatures in relevance theory are also primarily defined in terms of their relationship to another concept. in the relevance theory, the implicature is essentially any communicated assumption which is not an explicature. relevance theorists do note, but that the conceptual content of implicatures must be wholly inferred (carston 2000; sperber and wilson 2002), and to be inferred they must be intended by the speaker, and be understood by the listener as intended (sperber and wilson 2002; papafragou 2002).implicature in the relevance theoretic framework is a much more restricted concept than in gricean and neo-gricean approaches, as it primarily encompasses only particularised conversational implicatures. the relevance theorists have argued that phenomena which are termed short-circuited implicatures (groefsema 1992), conventional implicatures (wilson and sperber 1993), and metaphor/metonymy (carston 1996, 2000) all contribute to the explicatures of utterances, and are thus not actually examples of implicature. though it is not entirely clear, it also appears that some examples of generalised conversational implicatures are treated as explicatures, while others are treated as implicatures by relevance theorists (carston , 1998b). in example (1) the portion in the square brackets is considered to be the explicature by relevance theorists, but a generalised conversational implicature by the neo- griceans.(1) bill drank a bottle of vodka and as a result fell into a stupor (carston 2001: 21).however, the status of the inferred element in brackets in example (2) is not so clear.carston (2001: 22) seems tempted to call it an example of an explicature, but sperber and wilson (2002: 4), on the other hand, seem to characterise it as an implicature.(2) some but not all of the children were sick (carston 2001: 22). hamblin (1999) and gibbs and moise (1997) tested a number of different generalized conversational implicatures finding that they were considered to be part of what is said, rather than implicatures by ordinary speakers. gibbs (2000) has argued that these results support the relevance theoretic distinction between implicature and explicature.but these kinds of intuitions provide a valuable starting point, one should be careful in analyzing which intuitions are actually being tapped into in those kinds of experiments. what ordinary speakers consider to be what is said depends on how one elicits the response. what is said is commonly interpreted in two ways: in an indirect-quotational sense and in a commitment sense. (wilson and sperber 2000: 253) whats more? other experiments state that ordinary speakers may perceive unequivocal examples of implicature to be a part of what the speaker has said in some cases. those results indicate that the intuitions about what is said may actually overlap with what is implicated.moreover while relevance theorists have stated that more pragmatic processes are involved in communication than was previously assumed, in their rush to reduce all the different types of the pragmatic phenomena into the two relevance theoretic categories of implicature and explicature, important characteristics of various pragmatic phenomena have been neglected. for instance, the request arising from “can you pass the salt?” is an explicature rather than a short-circuited implicature. however this argument is weakened by the fact that there isnt mention at all of the potential politeness effects associated with can you? as a request. and it is hard to see how one will explain politeness effects in account where an utterance like can you pass the salt? is treated in the same manner as the utterance like can you swim?. so there is no explanation of why only the former give rise to politeness effects in many contexts, and if both types of interpretation of can arise in the same manner to generate explicatures. an important feature of these sorts of examples is that they give rise to politeness effects, something that is missed in the current relevance theoretic treatment of the phenomenon.the relevance theorists have put many pragmatic phenomena that neo-griceans have identified as generalised conversational implicatures, conventional implicatures, short-circuited implicatures etc., all into the same category as what is literally said, namely the category of explicature. that is problematic in some cases, because a number of the phenomena identified as implicatures by neo-griceans have characteristics that distinguish them from what is literally said, however these characteristics are not recognized in a relevance theoretic analysis. whether all these phenomena should be treated as implicatures is a terminological issue which has not yet been resolved.the careful analysis of the different phenomena is required to ascertain the manner in that they should be approached to resolve thoose terminological debates. while lumping them altogether into the single category seems to be a premature move given the current state of empirical evidence about those phenomena. and in some cases it leads to researchers to miss the important distinctions that need to be made between different types of pragmatic phenomena.conclusionthe problem of whether the relevance theoretic distinction between explicature is overly reductive is not the only one facing
温馨提示
- 1. 本站所有资源如无特殊说明,都需要本地电脑安装OFFICE2007和PDF阅读器。图纸软件为CAD,CAXA,PROE,UG,SolidWorks等.压缩文件请下载最新的WinRAR软件解压。
- 2. 本站的文档不包含任何第三方提供的附件图纸等,如果需要附件,请联系上传者。文件的所有权益归上传用户所有。
- 3. 本站RAR压缩包中若带图纸,网页内容里面会有图纸预览,若没有图纸预览就没有图纸。
- 4. 未经权益所有人同意不得将文件中的内容挪作商业或盈利用途。
- 5. 人人文库网仅提供信息存储空间,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对用户上传分享的文档内容本身不做任何修改或编辑,并不能对任何下载内容负责。
- 6. 下载文件中如有侵权或不适当内容,请与我们联系,我们立即纠正。
- 7. 本站不保证下载资源的准确性、安全性和完整性, 同时也不承担用户因使用这些下载资源对自己和他人造成任何形式的伤害或损失。
最新文档
- 2025年度重点工程土石方工程居间服务费标准范本
- 2025版滕彩离婚协议书附离婚协议签订及履行监督服务
- 2025版涉外法律事务处理及咨询合同下载
- 2025版全国离婚协议书审查与鉴定合同
- 2025版土地拍卖后续服务合同示范文本
- 2025版老旧小区改造工程外包施工合同范本
- 2025年切削钻机租赁及智能化改造服务合同
- 2025年度关键岗位保密及禁止同行业竞争协议
- 2025年度电工电气设备租赁与维护服务合同
- 2025版在线医疗健康服务平台采购与推广合同
- 子宫内膜癌医师教学查房市公开课一等奖课件省赛课获奖课件
- 膝痹中医护理方案效果总结分析报告
- 铸造基础知识及常见铸造缺陷简介演示
- 中式烹调师(高级技师考试资料)
- 仓储技术与库存理论简论
- 日地空间灾害性天气的发生发展和预报研究课件
- 西安大唐不夜城的项目整体推广的策略提案的报告课件
- 可下载打印的公司章程
- 少先队辅导员工作记录表(共7页)
- 公开课教学评价表
- 消防验收规范标准(最新完整版)19844
评论
0/150
提交评论